In
my previous post,
I presented and responded to some more objections to the argument
about regulation of cognitive enhancement (CE) and the economic
disincentives model (EDM).
Namely,
there has been a considerable amount of constructive
criticism
regarding my proposal.
Some neuroethicists
took
issue with my favoring prohibitive policies to dangerous CE drugs
such as
Amphetamine (e.g. Adderall), while
others took issue with the conclusion that EDM
could be an option for public policy on extended release forms of
Methylphenidate (e.g. Ritalin SR).
In two separate posts I have answered these objections.
In
this post I'll explore and respond to several objections from
neuroethicists who think my argument on policy options in general and EDM in particular
are failing to address the relevant issues in regulation of CE: Jamie
Nicole LaBuzetta, Brewer
& De Grote, and Jessica
Flanigan.
LaBuzetta
on the ethics of a better “Smart Drug”
Jamie
Nicole LaBuzzeta argees that the case for regulation of Ritalin and
Adderall is compeling. However, she thinks that it can nevertheless
problematic when the same rationale is applied to other drugs with
improved risk to benefit ratios. When applied to safer ‘smart
drugs’ such as modafinil, an evidence-based regulatory model might
actually seem to compel their use. Such a compulsion would be
contrary to the very idea of liberty and autonomy, but perhaps there
are other ideas and values that should take precedence.
She
argues that
it
is plausible and reasonable to demand
from
individuals working in high-responsibility roles, such as military,
medical, and aeronautical professions to use a safe and effective
cognitive enhancing medication, such as modafinil. She considers
different principles that could support her conclusion and opts for
Utilitarianism.
Reply
to LaBuzetta
First of all, I am well
aware that, due to reasons of space, my
article on Ritalin and Adderall, left out some very important CE
drugs, such as Modafinil. However, I believe that EDM can be
successfully extended to most new CE drugs that are not too dangerous
and/or addictive. The reason for this is that newer CE drugs are
likely to have many unknown effects. Even if clinical studies prove
they are safe and effective for specific pathologies, the data on
effects of prolonged use needs to be somehow generated. EDM, with the
requirement of annual medical testing and additional insurance is
specifically designed to fill that gap.
Limits of Utilitarianism
Regarding mandatory use
by certain professions such as military pilots, LaBuzetta is right to
note that these are issues that EDM did not tackle. Indeed, military
pilots are frequently ordered to take even dangerous amphetamines on
prolonged combat missions. However, I think that her choice for
Utilitarianism as the right ethical framework for regulating these
specific cases is problematic, because it demands too much
information and cognitive resources for decision making which is not
available and thus is not feasible.
Foreseeable consequences
are not enough
Utilitarianism
requires that all alternative responses are considered, to calculate
all consequences of all identified options, to predict and develop
contingency plans for all unintended consequences, and to calculate
the probability that a certain response sets a precedent for other
circumstances where the information may be less reliable. All
this creates a nice optimization model, but no mind or machine can
solve moral problems in this way. In the real world, even with
“safer” smart drugs we just don't know enough to rely on
foreseeable consequences alone. That is why in any discussion on
regulatory options, in addition to consequences, we need to take
rights and virtues seriously.
However,
others have different objections: even if we opt for deontological
principles, such as justice, EDM may fail to promote it.
Brewer
and De Grote on EDM and social inequality
Cameron
Brewer and Heather De Grote argue that if principles of bio-medical
ethics are considered more thoroughly (specifically, the principles
of justice
and non-maleficence), EDM must be rejected. They
claim that EDM is at odds with the “fair opportunity” rule: it
would deny
the social benefits of enhancement on the basis of undeserved
disadvantageous properties. They
grant that some form of “discourage use” model might be
applicable,
but that it should not be as costly to the consumer as EDM.
Brewer's
and De Grote's other objections
According
to Brewer and De Grote, EDM would almost certainly create an even
greater gap between the haves and have-nots. It would effectively
deny the social benefits of extended release formulas of
methylphenidate to the economically disadvantaged. Furthermore,
they argue that EDM would harm the interests of the disadvantaged, as
it would exacerbate the already increasing academic achievement
gap between the rich and the poor. EDM would ensure that only those
with higher incomes
would be able to buy and use methylphenidate, while the poor would
have to keep their uphill struggle for academic achievement without
it.
Reply
to Brewer and De Grote
Since
EDM has been developed precisely as a means to protect the rights and
interests of the disadvantaged, this is a serious objection. However,
Brewer's and De Grote's argument would only be convincing if EDM
would make CE drugs so expensive as to be unaffordable for the poor.
Consider once more the analogy with tobacco: discourage use policies
on tobacco introduces taxes, which are sometimes very high. In
Norway, they amount to 200%. And yet, even though cigarettes are not
cheap, most smokers in Norway
live in poorer regions and earn low incomes. Now, it is obvious that
extra taxation did not make tobacco unaffordable to the poor. Indeed,
EDM envisions that
the prices of CE drugs would be regulated: they would contain the
standard costs of production and distribution, the profit margin
would be limited and an additional tax would be imposed. This means
that regulation could be fine-tuned if it turns out that the poor are
disadvantaged in academic achievement due to the price of CE drugs.
Do CE drugs offer advantages or disadvantages?
An additional
problem for Brewer's and De Grote's objection is that they seem to
assume that CE drugs would offer only a competitive advantage, and no
health disadvantages. This is problematic in several respects. Even
though nicotine can also be seen as a mild cognitive enhancer, it
offers mostly health disadvantages. Given that stimulants are known
to cause nervousness,
drowsiness, insomnia, adverse effects during pregnancy, and even
serious cardiovascular adverse events, ignoring these effects as
potential disadvantages seriously undermines the argument. Indeed,
EDM's requirements of training and licensing for CE users actually
protect the interests and rights of the disadvantaged, who are
frequently targeted by promotional practices of industry which
promise social and other advantages by use of their product. That is
why I find the argument that EDM would be rejected based on the
principle of fair
opportunity unconvincing.
But,
maybe autonomy should take precedence over justice, and perhaps my
argument for different regulatory responses fails to respect autonomy
sufficiently.
Flanigan
on respect for autonomy and epistemic position of regulators
Jessica
Flanigan argues
that even
amphetamine and instant release forms of methylphenidate should be
legally available
because 1) prohibitions of recreational drugs are disrespectful to
users 2) even addicts are sufficiently autonomous with respect to
their choice to use drugs and 3) regulators are not in the best
epistemic position to judge whether the risks of amphetamine and
instant release forms of methylphenidate
warrant prohibition. She insists that even though some drugs
reliably undermine users’ life-plans and autonomous capacities,
policymakers should nevertheless permit drug use because the
appropriate response to the value of autonomy is respect, not to
promote autonomy.
Flanigan's
other objections
Flanigan
also thinks that my argument rests on a dubious characterization of
the psychology of addiction, as some empirical evidence suggests that
addicts are autonomous when they choose to use drugs. Finally, she
claims that it is illiberal to permit or prohibit drugs based on a
judgment about whether the potential benefits to the user justify the
risks users face. Her view is that consumers have the authority to
decide for themselves whether it is worth it to risk their health for
the sake of pharmacological benefits, either for enhancement or
recreation.
Reply to Flanigan
Even though I agree with
Flanigan that autonomy is very important, and that the state needs to
respect it, I disagree with her view on what such respect entails.
Consider
the following analogy: many individuals might find explosives and
rocket-launchers helpful or fascinating for their rational
life-plans, and these could
be used responsibly (e.g. as a part of weapons collection or for
leveling the ground). However, the threat of irresponsible use of
such objects is such a danger to others that the state is justified
in prohibiting possession of rocket launchers and explosives by
members of the general public. As it is reasonable to endorse a
system in which people are not allowed to walk around with explosives
and rocket-launchers, it is perfectly rational and in accordance to
autonomy to limit availability of amphetamines.
Respect
for autonomy suitably defined
Namely,
a substance for which there is overwhelming empirical proof that it
can impair cognitive and volitional capacities (the presuppositions
of autonomy), and cause aggression, erratic and violent behavior, is
not (and should not be) subject only to the authority of the
consumer. However, in my article
I do note the need to respect even some of the more self-destructive
wishes of competent adults. Indeed, I have concluded that when a
person does
voluntarily and autonomously choose to consume amphetamines with full
knowledge of their addictive properties and harmful physiological and
social consequences, the society would only be legitimate in
punishing the producers and distributors of these drugs, but not the
users.
Having
answered the questions and issues raised by the authors who find
faults with my argument and EDM, it is time to respond to additional
points of view. Namely, instead of focusing on shortcomings, some
neuroethicists have offered constructive suggestions on how the
argument and model might be improved. So
what do they suggest? And how do I respond? Stay tuned to find out...