![]() |
« October 2015 | Main | December 2015 »
![]() |
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/30/2015 at 03:44 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by Adam Kolber on 11/30/2015 at 08:57 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Moral cognition can be fast or slow. But recent research in cognitive science suggests that for moral thinking to be done well, a third type of cognition is needed: critical thinking. Does this mean it is time for triple process moral psychoogy? I think the answer is yes.
Over the past decade, dual-process theories of cognition have become the dominant empirical paradigm for understanding moral judgment and reasoning. These theories aim to understand moral thinking in terms of two separate mental subsystems: one slow and analytic, the other quick and crude. Both types of processing suffer from complementary defects: the former system is adaptive and efficient, but prone to error; the latter is flexible and sophisticated, but its power is limited, and its deployment costly. However, it has proven surprisingly difficult for dual-process theories of moral judgment to deliver on their main promise of bringing the tools of empirical psychology to bear on the question which moral rules and principles make sense, and which would be better given up.
I believe that moral thinking and reasoning are only insufficiently understood when described in terms of a quick but intuitive and a slow but rational type of cognition. This approach severely underestimates the importance and impact of dispositions to initiate and engage in critical thinking – the cognitive resource in charge of counteracting my-side bias, closed-mindedness, dogmatism, and breakdowns of self-control. Moral cognition is based, not on emotion and reason, but on an integrated network of intuitive, algorithmic and reflective thinking.
Let me spell out this idea in a little more detail. Some judgments are made quickly and effortlessly, others require deliberate thought. Dual Process Theories (DPT) in cognitive science capitalize on this observation, and argue that the human mind consists of two subsystems (Evans 2003, 2008): System I processes information automatically, intuitively, and without drawing on scarce cognitive resources. System II works slowly, analytically, and requires controlled conscious processing (Kahneman 2012).
What does this model entail for moral cognition? Are moral judgments based on intuition and emotion (Haidt 2001, Prinz 2007)? Or are they grounded in reason and conscious deliberation (Kennett 2009, Sauer 2012)? Many philosophers and psychologists hope that DPT will help us shed light on these issues, and allow us to address questions such as whether morality is relative, or whether moral norms can be rationally justified.
Existing dual process theories suffer from various problems (Evans and Stanovich 2013): the criteria for distinguishing System I and II are often vague; System I is not a unified system, but really a set of autonomous modules. More importanly, however, DPT overlooks the fact that System II must be further differentiated into an algorithmic and a reflective system (Stanovich 2009). The former is in charge of the tools that allow us to override non-normative default responses generated by the intuitive system. The latter is reponsible for the dispositions of critical thinking that initiate and monitor this override. This distinction is so important that some have proposed a move towards triple process accounts of cognition. But, unlike dual process theory, these developments have not yet been applied to issues in moral psychology. I think this gap should be closed by investigating the prospects of triple process moral psychology (TPMP). Critical thinking is one of the main aspects of competent moral judgment. TPMP will make it possible to conceptualize the significance of reflective thinking for moral agency, and to develop an account of human moral cognition that is both empirically informed and normatively satisfying.
It frequently remains unclear, for instance, when and why System II intervenes upon the intuitive reponse generated by System I, and whether such interventions tend to be detrimental or beneficial. Triple Process Theory is supposed to remedy this problem by arguing that System II is really comprised of two functionally separate systems. This is not just a terminological distinction: for one, the difference between the algorithmic and the reflective mind manifests in different patterns of breakdown (deficits in fluid intelligence vs. cognitive delusions); for another, reflective reasoning and algorithmic processing can be tapped by measuring performance on intelligence and critical thinking tasks, respectively, neither of which neatly predict performance on the other (Stanovich and West 2000).
The main function of System II is System I override: the default response generated by the intuitive system often needs to be intervened upon by conscious processing to arrive at the normative response. Crucially, however, this theory overlooks the fact that a) the need for such override has to be detected, b) the override itself needs to be initiated and c) the result of the override checked for accuracy. This higher level control is exercized on the basis of epistemic dispositions such as critical thinking, need for cognition, or open-mindedness. The initiation of default override is arguably the more fundamental process, yet the distinction between conscious processing and reflective self-criticism is lost on standard dual process models of moral judgment. Critical self-reflection is of central importance for moral psychology, since cognitive errors such as my-side bias, self-deception, or dogmatism are arguably most harmful in the moral domain.
This has far-reaching implications for the empirically informed study of moral cognition in both philosophy and psychology. Existing two-system approaches to moral judgment such as the Social Intuitionist model (Haidt 2001, 2008) or Joshua Greene’s dual process theory (2001, 2004, 2008) are either implausibly pessimistic about the influence of reasoning on moral judgment (Jacobson, Railton, Sauer) or suffer from a variety of empirical and conceptual issues (see Guy Kahane’s work on this; cf. Greene 2014). At the heart of both theories are accounts of intuition override: the main claim of the Social Intuitionist model suggests that such override happens surprisingly rarely (“moral dumbfounding”, Haidt 2001). Greene’s Dual Process account suggests that arriving at consequentialist responses often requires override of an emotionally more salient response. Yet neither of those theories offers a convincing account of when, why, and under what conditions such an override is initiated.
What are possible implications of this approach? For one, the distinction between rationalism and sentimentalism about moral judgment may well turn out to be scientifically obsolete. Another, perhaps more surprising upshot of TPMP may be that the influence of reason on moral judgment needs to be reconsidered as well. Here, two questions need to be addressed: 1) is this influence frequent or rare? 2) Is this influence beneficial or detrimental? One possible answer suggested by TPMP could be that the influence of Type II processing is frequent, but tends to result in harmful rationalizations and moral disengagement; the influence of reflective Type III processing, on the other hand, is beneficial, but tends to be rare. The resulting theory will be a form of rationalism with a pessimistic twist.
Posted by Hanno Sauer on 11/30/2015 at 05:25 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted on behalf of Saskia Nagel and Peter Reiner:
Call for Applications:Interdisciplinary Research Week "Pediatric Neuro-Enhancement - Ethical, social and legal questions in comparison between North America and Germany"Institute of Cognitive Science (IKW), University of Osnabrück, March 7-11, 2016The Institute of Cognitive Science at the University of Osnabrück hosts a research week for young researchers funded by the German Ministry of Education and Research. Renowned experts from Canada, the UK, and Germany will present and discuss the topic throughout the whole week. Besides discussions with international experts and the collaborative development of an international study, participants will receive intensive, interdisciplinary feedback on their work.Young researchers (postdocs and PhD students) from the neurosciences, medicine, psychology, pedagogics, philosophy, theology, law, and social sciences are cordially invited to apply for participation in the research week. The research week will be held in English.International Experts:Roi Cohen Kadosh, Department of Experimental Psychology, OxfordManfred Döpfner, Neurology and Psychiatry, University Hospital ColognePeter Reiner, National Core for Neuroethics, VancouverIlina Singh, Department of Psychiatry, OxfordApplication Guidelines:We invite you to send your application (1 page abstract for the planned contribution, 1 page short CV with publications) as .pdf-file to the organizer Dr. Saskia Nagel. We are looking forward to applications that show connections to the topic, previous work, and readiness for intensive and interdisciplinary exchange.Closing date for applications: December 13, 2015Costs for travel and accommodation will be covered. Professional childcare will be ensured. The revised versions of the presentations will be published as an edited volume soon after the research week. All participants are asked to submit their contributions by July 2016. They will receive an allowance of 300 Euro.For further information, see http://ikw.uni-osnabrueck.de/~neuroenhancement/neuroenhancement_call_en.pdfContact:Dr. Saskia K. NagelInstitute of Cognitive Science, University of OsnabrückAlbrechtstrasse 28D-49076 OsnabrückGermany
Posted by Adam Kolber on 11/25/2015 at 09:13 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
![]() |
Last Edition's Most Popular Article(s):
In The Popular Press:
In the Academic Literature:
|
||
|
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/22/2015 at 05:45 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/20/2015 at 04:04 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
The New Scientist reported that a computer program was able to predict lying 75 percent of the time, relative to 59.5 percent for humans.
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/17/2015 at 03:53 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/17/2015 at 03:15 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/16/2015 at 04:40 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
![]() |
Last Edition's Most Popular Article(s):
In The Popular Press:
In the Academic Literature:
|
||
|
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/16/2015 at 03:53 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
People love to hate on trolley dilemmas. In this post, I will hate on them, too, but in a slightly more awkward, indirect and clumsy fashion. That is, I will hate on it just like a philosopher would.
Trolleyology – as the use of scenarios involving runaway trolleys threatening to kill faceless strangers is sometimes polemically referred to – employs far-fetched thought experiments to test our moral intuitions. These outlandish cases typically feature some “moral emergency” (Appiah) in which innocent people are endangered by some deadly force, and it just so happens that you have to make the trade-off between, say, saving one person or five. Sometimes, you can save the five by pulling a switch and diverting a trolley. Sometimes, you have to actively kill someone to bring about the puportedly more optimific result.
The details of this paradigm do not interest me here. What matters to me is the most widespread complaint against this philosophical method, which is based on its lack of realism. Critics of trolleyology like to point out that these scenarios are so utterly strange, so far removed from our everday experience and the physical and psychological laws that obtain within it, that the intuitions we may have about such scenarios are useless at best, and perniciously misleading at worst.
Defenders of trolleyology like to reply, simply, that this is irrelevant. What is of interest to moral philosophers is not people’s intuitions about this or that unrealistic case. It is the fact that people make robust contrastive judgments about two or more similar but subtly different cases. That is the real finding, for which the level of realism of the individual scenarios (Switch, Footbridge, etc.) has no bearing at all.
It is this last point that I find unconvincing. After all, what is it that the lack of realism objection comes down to? I find it useful to distinguish five versions of this objection: ecological validity, novelty, imaginative resistance, excessive specificity, and the blurring of the distinction between criterial and non-criterial reasons. According to the first, people’s intuitions about far-fetched scenarios are evidentially useless because they do not translate into judgments about real-world scenarios. But if this is correct, then why would contrasts in people’s judgments translate in this way? I think that they don’t. This problem, I believe, applies to the other four versions as well. If people’s judgments are tainted by the extreme unfamiliarity of the cases people are asked to make a judgment about, then contrasts in their judgments are tainted in the same way. If these scenarios are excessively specific, and thus too fine-grained for our moral intuitions to handle, or if they are too strange for subjects to imagine them fully and properly, or if they require subjects to base their judgments on a class of reasons (criterial reasons that stipulate full and flawless information) they are not used to dealing with, then all of these problems affect the contrasts in people’s judgments as well.
The lack of realism objection is the most serious indictment there is for Trolleyologists. The “contrastive responses matter, realism doesn’t” is their best response. But if the argument sketched above is correct, this response fails – and with it, the use of many, if not most, far-fetched thought experiments.
Posted by Hanno Sauer on 11/12/2015 at 09:15 AM | Permalink | Comments (4)
For more information:
Sydney Law School| Professional Learning & Community Engagement T +61 2 9351 0429 | E [email protected]
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/10/2015 at 10:34 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/10/2015 at 10:30 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
![]() |
Last Edition's Most Popular Article(s):
In The Popular Press:
In the Academic Literature:
|
||
|
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/08/2015 at 10:33 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by NELB Staff on 11/07/2015 at 10:30 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)