|
« September 2015 | Main | November 2015 »
|
Posted by NELB Staff on 10/23/2015 at 04:26 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Consequentializers argue that all moral theories can be consequentialized. This means that for every non-consequentialist normative theory, we can construct an identical consequentialist counterpart that has the same deontic output (it is extensionally equivalent, and classifies exactly the same actions as right or wrong, respectively). The recipe is simple: take consequentialist theory C; here is a counterexample E to C; take E, and model it as another bad consequence. This gives you C’. Your non-consequentialist intuition expressed by E has been swallowed. An example: start with classical utilitarianism (C); C entails that it can be can be permissible to break promises when doing so is for the greater good (E); build “breaking promises” into your theory of the good by declaring that promise-breaking counts as a bad consequence (C’).
I think that this strategy rests on a deep misunderstanding of what moral theory does. If adopted, it would deprive consequentialism of all its justificatory and explanatory strength.
Consider an analogy. Think about our reply to someone with Kantian proclivities who argues that all moral theories can be deontologized. We can, this Kantian says, incorporate any counterexample to her moral standard (that for some maxim or principle to be morally permissible, it must be possible to think/will it to be a universal law) by changing our theory of value in a way that is analogous to the one consequentializers recommend. Consequentializers hold that we can consequentialize putative counterexamples by amending our theory of value. In the case of consequentialism, this means that we add an item (e. g. promise-breaking) to our list of things which constitute a bad consequence. Since Kantians famously ground what is good in what is right rather than the other way round, to deontologize something would thus mean to make an analogous move by simply adding something to our list of what makes something wrong.
Suppose Kantians argue that lying is never morally permissible. Now someone presents a possible counterexample: a group of homicidal thugs are knocking on your door, in pursuit of an innocent stranger whom you are hiding in your attic. If lying is never permissible, then one may not lie even to this group of would-be murderers – obviously, this is too much to bear, so (this version of) Kantianism must be false. Not so fast!, replies the Kantian; I will simply deontologize your counterexample by adding “lying to a group of murderous thugs in pursuit of an innocent individual” to my list of things which are wrong, just as consequentializers take themselves to be entitled to add things to their list of things which are bad.
In this deontological case, this move would clearly strike us as unacceptably ad hoc. Why is this? We want a deontological moral theory to show why certain acts are wrong on the basis of an independently justified theory of rightness – in this case, the theory that what makes an action permissible is that its maxim can be universalized without contradiction in willing or conception. This explanatory and justificatory step is missing in the deontologization method just described. Yet the analogous strategy is precisely the one advocated by consequentializers.
Posted by Hanno Sauer on 10/22/2015 at 06:00 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
The results of a sleep study of "technologically primitive" cultures suggests that people of those cultures sleep on average no longer than people of cultures with abundant electronic lighting and other stimulation, as summarized by this news article.
Posted by NELB Staff on 10/21/2015 at 07:55 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by NELB Staff on 10/19/2015 at 07:54 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
|
Last Edition's Most Popular Article(s):
In The Popular Press:
In the Academic Literature:
Upcoming Events:
|
||
|
Posted by NELB Staff on 10/17/2015 at 04:10 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Posted by NELB Staff on 10/15/2015 at 04:09 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Interesting! See here.
Posted by Adam Kolber on 10/14/2015 at 08:57 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
|
Last Edition's Most Popular Article(s):
In The Popular Press:
In the Academic Literature:
Upcoming Events:
|
||
|
Posted by NELB Staff on 10/12/2015 at 04:09 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Sometimes, we offer reasons to believe a proposition isn’t true. Other times, we adduce reasons to show that it isn’t justified, or that someone isn’t justified in holding it. The former are often called rebutting, the latter undercutting defeaters. This post is about the latter category.
In many cases, undercutting defeaters take the form of debunking explanations: they aim to point out that, given the way a subject (or group) arrived at her belief(s), those beliefs are unlikely to be true. Marx, Nietzsche and Freud are perhaps the most influential debunkers, but traces of this method can already be found in Xenophanes’ anthropomorphism objection.
Debunking explanations pose a reliability challenge: if S arrived at p using method M, but using M is unlikely to “track the truth” with regard to p, p is unjustified. Debunking explanations account for the causal genesis of a (set of) beliefs in terms of off-track processes. If you ask me how many chairs there are in the building next door, and I guess 384, then I have used an unreliable method to arrive at this belief. And if I were to figure out what I ought to do, morally speaking, by consulting the emotions and intuitions my evolutionary history has disposed me to find plausible, my moral judgments would be unjustified. Yet this is precisely the situation proponents of so-called evolutionary debunking arguments think we are in. We think that pain is bad and that we have stronger obligations towards our children than to strangers. But in principle, the moral facts could be anything; so how likely is it that selective pressures, which we have no reason to believe to be truth-tracking with regard to moral facts, would give us true moral beliefs? Fantastically unlikely, debunkers suggest. And so our moral beliefs are unjustified.
But notice that we can only be off-track if there is a track to be on. In an extremely influential paper from 2006, Sharon Street has shown that reliability challenges need not undermine the justification we have for our (moral) judgments. At least, she suggests, if we are willing to sacrifice something else instead. If we are prepared to change our metaethics – that is, the beliefs we have about our beliefs – then we can leave our normative ethics – that is, our substantive moral beliefs themselves – intact. Metaethics can protect our moral beliefs from debunking.
I wish to suggest that this is a mistake. First, notice how utterly strange this suggestion sounds. If your method for arriving at a belief is bad, don’t give up that belief. Change your account of what it is that makes this belief true! In a more recent paper, Street acknowledges this herself:
“That move might seem odd. It’s as though upon learning that your belief [that Hayes was the 20th president of the US] about Hayes [the 19th president of the US, H.S.] had its origin in hypnosis, you find it so implausible that you could be wrong about whether Hayes was the twentieth president that you opt to change your conception of the subject matter, concluding that facts about who was the twentieth president are constituted by facts about who you think the twentieth president was, no matter what the source of your views, hypnotism included.”
What could possibly be the reason for what seems, on the face of it, to be an epistemically obscene suggestion? Street argues that we can make a pick. Evolutionary explanations of the origin of our moral judgments, metaethical realism about those judgments, and belief in those judgments are an inconsistent triad. What gives? Street suggests realism has to go, because it is the smallest sacrifice:
“The evolutionary theory of our origins is overwhelmingly supported by our best science. Taking that as a fixed point, I suggest that it is much more plausible to think that a mind-independent conception of value is false than it is to think that we have no idea how to live, which is the conclusion that results if we pair a mind-independent conception of value with an evolutionary genealogy of valuing. Accepting this radical sceptical conclusion would involve nothing less than suspending all evaluative judgment, and either continuing to move about but regarding oneself as acting for no reason at all, or else sitting paralyzed where one is and just blinking in one’s ignorance of how to go forward. Accepting the conclusion that value is mind-dependent, on the other hand, preserves many or our evaluative views – allowing us to see why we are reasonably reliable about matters of value – while at the same time allowing us to see ourselves as evolved creatures.”
But notice that, in assessing which of the aforementioned three links is the weakest, Street appeals to pragmatic considerations first and foremost. These pragmatic considerations, I wish to suggest, are the problem here. Since evolutionary theory is non-negotiable, and moral skepticism pragmatically and deliberatively unacceptable, realism should be given up. Why? Because giving up our substantive moral beliefs rather than our realist metaethics would be too much to bear – it would paralyze, confuse, and depress us, leaving us with “no idea how to live”.
But so what? Firstly, pragmatic reasons seem to be of the wrong kind. We want to know which is true – realism or our moral beliefs. Which of the two is more important or pleasant to us seems neither here nor there with regard to this question. (Compare tbe belief I have cancer.) Secondly, if pragmatic considerations are admissible, and indeed decisive in this context, why not sacrifice evolution? Whether or not evolutionary theory is true has the smallest pragmatic significance, after all. (Consider that people did perfectly fine without believing in evolution for, well, a long time.) Thirdly, I see no reason why being unable to take moral values and norms seriously should yield the predicted result. (Consider psychopaths, who certainly aren’t paralyzed and depressed. If anything, their impoverished moral repertoire seems to make them hyperagential.)
I think that for the three reasons mentioned above, Street’s strategy fails. But why would one think that the “odd move” she suggests should be plausible to begin with? This, I suggest, is due to an unbalanced diet of examples. When we compare the plausibility of metaethical realism to how compelling we find beliefs such as Pain is bad or Cheaters should be shunned, realism has to go. But when we compare realism to beliefs such as Incest is immoral or Strangers should be met with hostility, the balance tips in the other direction. Debunking arguments can be deployed selectively in just this way: sometimes, they can undermine our first-order beliefs; sometimes, they can target the beliefs we have about those beliefs. Metaethics can protect our moral beliefs from debunking, but only when we have reason to want it to.
Posted by Hanno Sauer on 10/12/2015 at 09:13 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
|
Last Edition's Most Popular Article(s):
In The Popular Press:
In the Academic Literature:
Upcoming Events:
|
||
|
Posted by NELB Staff on 10/08/2015 at 04:07 PM | Permalink | Comments (0)
The Brain, hosted by David Eagleman, to air on PBS beginning Oct. 14.
Posted by Adam Kolber on 10/07/2015 at 10:31 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
If I put poison into your coffee and you die, I did nothing wrong. That is, if I mistakenly thought it was sugar, and I had no reason to believe it was poison, I deserve no blame. Factual ignores excuses -- ignorantia facti excusat. Things start to look very different, however, if we consider a second case: I put poison into your coffee and you die. This time, I did know it was poison, but I didn’t believe that poisoning you was wrong. I suggest that we are far less inclined to accept this as an excuse – ignorantia legis non excusat. Call this difference in the respective exculpatory powers of moral and ordinary ignorance the asymmetry.
Recently, there has been a lot of discussion on whether this is actually true, or whether we should grant non-culpable moral ignorance comparable exculpatory force. Those who wish to reject the asymmetry typically draw on cases in which an individual’s social environment or the inherent complexity of a case make it particularly difficult to get things right, morally speaking. For instance, in a series of papers, Gideon Rosen (2004) has used ancient Hittite slave owners or mid-century sexists as examples to illustrate that there may be some cases in which people’s non-culpable moral ignorance may exempt them from blame.
I first stumbled upon the observation that there is something strange about the exculpatory force of moral ignorance in a paper by John Mikhail (2007), where he claimed that the asymmetry was part of our universal moral grammar, pointing to evidence that children as young as five already draw this distinction. But one question that, to my best knowledge at least, has been completely overlooked so far concerns the metaethical implications of this observation. For instance, if moral realism is true, and there are mind-independent moral facts, why should such facts not have the same exculpatory force as non-moral facts? Frankly, I see no reason why this should be so.
I think we can use the asymmetry to develop a novel challenge to robust forms of moral realism. Here is the basic outline of this challenge:
The Asymmetry Argument
(1) If there are mind-independent moral facts, then being non-culpably ignorant of them should have exculpatory power comparable to being non-culpably ignorant of non-moral facts.
(2) Being non-culpably ignorant of the mind-independent moral facts does not have exculpatory power comparable to being ignorant of non-moral facts.
(3) Therefore, there are no mind-independent moral facts.
To escape this problem, realists can either deny (1) or (2). But I think neither of these options really work. I cannot go into details here, because things get complicated really quickly, but the gist of my argument is that the counterexamples realists may use to reject (2) – children, individuals with mental disorders, psychopaths, or cases involving circumstantial moral luck of the kind mentioned above – all backfire. In all these cases, it is controversial i) whether moral ignorance excuses, ii) whether moral ignorance excuses (or whether factual ignorance is doing all the work here) or whether iii) if we grant that children or psychopaths are excused on the basis of genuine moral ignorance, this is so because of their inability to appreciate mind-independent moral facts, or whether it is due to the fact that they suffer from impaired or immature emotional sensibilities. I argue that the latter, non-cognitivist explanation is far more plausible.
So the realist can move on to rejecting premise (1), and attempt to explain (rather than deny) the asymmetry in realism-friendly ways. I argue that this strategy is even less promising. As I see it, there are essentially two ways to accommodate the datum. One is pragmatic, and aims to explain the asymmetry in more or less consequentialist terms. The other is epistemic, and is based on the idea that the way we gain cognitive access to mind-independent moral facts is such that the asymmetry should come as no surprise. Pragmatic explanations draw on the fact that it is prudent not to grant moral ignorance any (or at least not much) exculpatory force because doing so would always give everyone a watertight excuse for everything, and this would be undesirable. But why, if realism is true, would this be so? The only explanation I can think of is that, unlike cases of ordinary ignorance, we could never point to any publicly available evidence (X was present at the scene, looked in the right direction, lighting conditions were normal) that someone must have been in a position to know some moral fact. This, I suspect, is because recognizing moral truths has nothing to do with finding out what the mind-independent facts are at all.
Epistemic explanations of the asymmetry fare just as badly. One may be tempted to suggest that the exculpatory force of various types of ignorance tracks degrees of difficulty. On this suggestion, non-culpable moral ignorance does not excuse because acquiring moral knowledge is so easy: either, moral facts are easy to come by (availability) or obvious (triviality). I think neither of these options is independently convincing or indeed hepful to the realist. In general, I do not think that obtaining moral knowledge is easy, as this would be implausibly optimistic and fail to explain both widespread moral disagreement as well as moral progress. Moreover, I do not think that according to the most plausible versions of moral realism, moral knowledge should be readily available or trivial. In fact, both naturalist (Cornell folks) and non-naturalist (Michael Huemer, David Enoch) moral realists explicitly say that moral knowledge is not easy or trivial.
As far as I can see, moral realism can neither deny nor explain the asymmetry in any satisfying way.
Posted by Hanno Sauer on 10/06/2015 at 05:42 AM | Permalink | Comments (7)
I was interviewed about Free Will as a Matter of Law for the Oral Arguments podcast, available here. Kudos to Christian Turner and Joseph Miller for a lively discussion.
Posted by Adam Kolber on 10/05/2015 at 09:21 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Three postdoc or postdoc-type positions described here.
Posted by Adam Kolber on 10/05/2015 at 09:15 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)
Details here.
Posted by Adam Kolber on 10/05/2015 at 09:10 AM | Permalink | Comments (0)